Subtitles section Play video Print subtitles Have you ever gathered the correct ingredients and tried to cook, following the recipe, only to unintentionally make a mistake, so the meal didn't turn out right? That's a bit like what happens with Propositional Fallacies in thinking and reasoning. Even if you start with the right facts (aka good ingredients), if your way of thinking (aka the recipe method) isn't right, you might end up with the wrong conclusion (aka a meal that's not what you expected). Let's dive into these fallacies and see how they can trick us, just like a recipe that doesn't work out. Hi, I am Shao Chieh Lo, welcome to What People Also ask where I compiled some fun facts to share with you, usually by conducting a lot of Googling. Today I want to talk about 3 propositional fallacies where the logical structure of an argument leads to false conclusions, even when the content of the argument might be partially correct. For each fallacy, I will give one everyday example, one historical example, and one example of Coke vs Pepsi just for fun and to demonstrate the concept. So let's start by defining What are Propositional fallacies? Propositional fallacies are a type of logical fallacy occurring in deductive reasoning, where errors in the logical structure of an argument lead to false conclusions, despite having true premises. These fallacies are distinct because they stem from errors in how propositions (aka statements that can be true or false) are combined or manipulated, not from the content of the premises themselves. They are considered formal fallacies, which means it's identifiable by examining the argument's form or structure, rather than its content. Examples include Affirming a Disjunct, Affirming the Consequent, and Denying the Antecedent. Unlike other fallacies that might involve incorrect facts or irrelevant information, propositional fallacies highlight the critical importance of correct logical formulation in deductive reasoning, demonstrating how true premises can still lead to false conclusions if structured improperly. So let's talk about our first propositional fallacy: What is Affirming a Disjunct? Affirming a Disjunct is a logical fallacy that occurs in a situation where there are two possibilities (aka disjuncts), and the confirmation of one is incorrectly taken to deny the other. This fallacy follows the format: "A or B is true; A is true; therefore, B is not true." It's a fallacy because both A and B could be true simultaneously. Everyday example: A person said, "It's raining outside, so either I take an umbrella or I will definitely get wet; since I'm taking an umbrella, it's impossible for me to get wet." This statement implies a false dichotomy: either taking an umbrella or getting wet, suggesting these outcomes are mutually exclusive. However, this is an oversimplification. In reality, taking an umbrella doesn't inherently prevent the possibility of getting wet, as other factors like wind could still lead to one getting wet. The fallacy lies in the assumption that by affirming one outcome (aka using an umbrella), the other (aka getting wet) becomes impossible. This example showcases a common logical error, where binary thinking obscures the possibility of overlapping or multiple outcomes. It highlights the need to recognize that actions and consequences are often not strictly linear or exclusive, reminding us of the complexities and nuances in everyday scenarios. This fallacy demonstrates how easy it is to overlook these subtleties in our reasoning processes. Historical example: The debate between determinism and free will is a longstanding and central theme in philosophy, engaging numerous thinkers over the centuries. The longstanding philosophical debate between determinism and free will exemplifies the fallacy of affirming the disjunct. This discourse questions whether human actions are predetermined or if individuals have the freedom to choose independently. A common misinterpretation is the oversimplified argument: "Either actions are determined, or they result from free will. Since causality exists, free will does not." This binary perspective fails to consider the potential coexistence or complex interaction of these concepts. Enlightenment thinkers like David Hume and Immanuel Kant played pivotal roles in this debate. Hume's compatibilism suggested that causality's existence doesn't negate free will, while Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason" proposed that free will could exist within moral actions, even in a deterministic physical world. The 20th-century resurgence of this debate, influenced by advancements in quantum mechanics and neuroscience, further questioned the strict dichotomy between determinism and free will. Philosophers like A.J. Ayer and Daniel Dennett explored the compatibility of these concepts, suggesting a framework where deterministic and free-will principles coexist. This debate's history highlights the error of affirming a disjunct, simplifying a nuanced issue into a binary choice, and overlooking the complexities and interplay between determinism and free will in human agency and cognition. Coke vs Pepsi example A Coke enthusiast might declare, "I love Coke, so it's impossible for me to enjoy Pepsi." This statement is an example of the logical fallacy known as affirming a disjunct. The error lies in the assumption that a preference for Coke inherently excludes the possibility of liking Pepsi. However, personal tastes are not mutually exclusive, and one can appreciate different brands for different qualities. On the other hand, a Pepsi supporter might argue, "Pepsi is my absolute favorite, which means Coke must taste awful." This is another instance of affirming a disjunct. The belief that a fondness for Pepsi automatically translates to a disdain for Coke is a flawed conclusion. Preferences are subjective, and liking one product does not necessarily mean disliking its competitors. Both these instances show a common cognitive error where individuals mistakenly assume that their preference for one option means an automatic rejection of the alternative. This fallacy overlooks the nuanced nature of personal tastes and preferences. What is Affirming the consequent? Affirming the consequent is a logical fallacy involving an incorrect inference from a conditional statement. It occurs when one reason that because the consequent (aka the "then" part of a conditional statement) is true, the antecedent (aka the "if" part) must also be true. This reasoning is flawed because it ignores other possible reasons for the consequent being true. Everyday example: Consider the statement: "If it is raining, the ground will be wet." An instance of affirming the consequent would be: "The ground is wet, therefore it must be raining." This conclusion is fallacious because there are other reasons the ground could be wet, such as a sprinkler system or a spilled bucket of water. The wet ground doesn't necessarily mean it's raining; it's just consistent with what would be the case if it were raining. Historical example: The Geocentric Theory rooted in ancient Greek philosophy, notably Aristotle's ideas, posited Earth at the universe's center and was further developed by Ptolemy in his 2nd-century work "Almagest." Ptolemy's model, integrating complex concepts like epicycles, became the prevailing astronomical view for over a millennium, intertwined with Christian theology in the Middle Ages and widely accepted in Islamic and Christian scholarly circles. This theory's endurance exemplifies the fallacy of affirming the consequent. Observations that celestial bodies appeared to revolve around Earth led to the erroneous conclusion that Earth must be the universe's center. This reasoning assumes a direct causality from consequence to cause without considering other possible explanations. The shift to the heliocentric model, initiated by Copernicus in the 16th century and solidified by Kepler and Galileo's 17th-century findings, challenged this fallacy. Their work provided evidence that directly contradicted the geocentric view, demonstrating the perils of affirming the consequent in scientific inquiry and highlighting how entrenched beliefs, both religious and philosophical, can hinder the acceptance of new paradigms. Coke vs Pepsi example A Coke enthusiast might say, "If a soda refreshes you, it must be Coke. You feel refreshed, so you must have had Coke." This argument is flawed because feeling refreshed can result from various sodas, not exclusively Coke. The supporter is erroneously asserting that the effect (feeling refreshed) confirms the cause (drinking Coke), disregarding other potential explanations. Similarly, a Pepsi advocate might argue, "A bold tasting soda is definitely Pepsi. This soda has a bold taste, so it must be Pepsi." This is a fallacious reasoning because boldness in taste can be attributed to many sodas, not just Pepsi. The Pepsi supporter is mistakenly affirming that the effect (bold taste) is a definitive indicator of the cause (being Pepsi), which is an oversimplification of the possible causes for a bold taste in sodas. What is Denying the antecedent? Denying the antecedent is a logical fallacy that occurs when, from a conditional statement, one incorrectly infers that if the antecedent (the "if" part) is false, then the consequent (the "then" part) must also be false. This form of reasoning is flawed because the consequent can still be true even if the antecedent is false. Everyday example: Someone said "If I study hard, I will pass the exam. I didn't study hard, so I will not pass the exam." This reasoning is fallacious because there are other ways to pass the exam besides studying hard, such as already knowing the material or making educated guesses. The absence of studying doesn't necessarily guarantee a failure; it just negates one specific path to success. This example demonstrates the error in concluding that the failure of the condition (studying hard) automatically leads to the failure of the outcome (passing the exam). Historical example: Euclidean geometry, dating back to around 300 BC with the Greek mathematician Euclid, forms the foundation of geometric understanding through his work "Elements." A central aspect of Euclidean geometry is the parallel postulate, stating that parallel lines never intersect. However, a historical misinterpretation, particularly in the early study of geometry, involved the logical fallacy of denying the antecedent. This fallacy manifested in the incorrect belief that if two lines are not parallel, they must intersect, neglecting the possibility of skew lines in three-dimensional space, which are non-parallel yet do not intersect as they lie in different planes. This early misconception underscores a limited understanding of geometry, primarily confined to two dimensions. The later development and formalization of three-dimensional geometry clarified this misunderstanding. Further advancements in the 18th and 19th centuries by mathematicians like Gauss, Riemann, and Lobachevsky, who explored non-Euclidean geometries, significantly broadened the scope of geometric principles beyond Euclid's original framework. This evolution of mathematical thought highlights the dynamic nature of the field and the rectification of misconceptions through deeper investigation and expanded perspectives. Coke vs Pepsi example The Coke enthusiast, named Clara, was known for her unwavering belief in the superiority of Coca-Cola. One sunny afternoon, while sitting at a local café, she declared, "If a drink is Coke, then it is undoubtedly delicious." However, when the waiter brought a tray of Sprite for the table next to them, Clara scoffed, "Since Sprite is not Coke, it cannot possibly be delicious." Across town, Peter, a die-hard Pepsi fan, was equally staunch in his opinions. "If a drink is Pepsi, it's the epitome of refreshment," he proclaimed at a neighborhood barbecue. When his friend offered him a chilled glass of Fanta, Peter said, "Since that's not Pepsi, it can't be refreshing." In both scenarios, Clara and Peter were victims of the logical fallacy known as denying the antecedent. They each believed that if a drink wasn't their preferred brand, it couldn't possess qualities like deliciousness or refreshment. This belief created a rift in their understanding of the vast world of flavors beyond the realms of Coke and Pepsi.
B2 pepsi coke fallacy logical reasoning wet 3 Most Common Propositional fallacies (With coke and pepsi debate examples) 51 1 Jay posted on 2023/11/28 More Share Save Report Video vocabulary