Subtitles section Play video
Professor Shelly Kagan: We've begun to turn to Plato's
dialogue Phaedo, and what I started doing last
time was sketching the basic outlines of Plato's
metaphysics--not so much to give a full investigation of
that--clearly we're not going to do that here--but just to
provide enough of the essential outlines of Plato's metaphysical
views so that we can understand the arguments that come up later
in the Phaedo, basically all of which or many
of which presuppose something--certain central
aspects about Plato's metaphysical views.
The key point behind his metaphysics then was the thought
that, in addition to the ordinary empirical physical
world that we're all familiar with,
we have to posit the existence of a kind of second realm,
in which exist the Platonic--as they're nowadays called--the
Platonic forms or Platonic ideas.
The sort of thing that perhaps we might call or think of as
abstract objects or abstract properties.
And the reason for positing these things is because we're
clearly able to think about these ideas,
and yet, we recognize that the ordinary physical
world--although things may participate in them to varying
degrees--we don't actually come across these objects or entities
in the physical world. So that we can talk about
things being beautiful to varying degrees,
but we never come across beauty itself in the actual empirical
world. We are able to talk about the
fact that two plus one equals three, but it's not as though we
ever come across numbers--number three itself--anywhere in the
empirical world. A further point that
distinguishes the empirical world from this--this realm of
Platonic ideal objects--is that indeed they--there's something
perfect about them. They don't change.
In contrast, physical objects are constantly
changing. Something might be short at one
point and become tall at another point, ugly at one point and
become beautiful--like the ugly duckling.
It starts out ugly and becomes a beautiful swan.
In contrast, justice itself never changes.
Beauty itself never changes. We have the thought that these
things are eternal, and indeed, beyond change,
in contrast to the empirical world.
In fact, if you start thinking more about the world from this
perspective, the world we live in is crazy.
It's almost insanely contradictory.
Plato thinks of it as crazy in the way that a dream is.
When you're caught up in the dream, you don't notice just how
insane it all is. But if you step back and
reflect on it, "Well, let's see,
I was eating a sandwich and suddenly the sandwich was the
Statue of Liberty, except the Statue of Liberty
was my mother. And she's flying over the
ocean, except she's really a piece of spaghetti."
That's how dreams are. And when you're in it,
it sort of all makes sense. Right?
You're kind of caught up, but you step back and say,
"That's just insane." Well, Plato thinks that the
empirical world has something of that kind of insanity,
something of that kind contradictoriness,
built into it that we don't ordinarily notice.
"He's a basketball player, so he's really,
really tall, except he's only six feet.
So he's really, really short for a basketball
player. This is a baby elephant,
so it's really, really big--except it's a baby
elephant, so it's really, really small."
The world is constantly rolling--this is a Platonic
expression--rolling between one form and the other.
And it's hard to make sense of. In contrast,
the mind is able to grasp the Platonic ideas,
the Platonic forms; and they're stable,
they're reliable, they are--they're law-like and
we can grasp them. They don't change;
they're eternal. That's, as I say,
the Platonic picture. Now, it's not my purpose here
to try to argue for or against Platonism with regard to
abstract entities. As I suggested in talking about
the example of math last time, it's not a silly view,
even if it's not a view that we all take automatically.
But in thinking about math, most of us are inclined to be
Platonists. We all do believe something
makes it true that two plus one equals three,
but it's not the fact that empirical objects--We don't do
empirical experiments to see whether two plus one equals
three. Rather, we think our mind can
grasp the truths about numbers. Plato thought everything was
like that. Well, I'm not going to argue
for and against that view--just wanted to sketch it,
so as to understand the arguments that turn on it.
So for our purposes, let's suppose Plato was right
about that and ask, what follows?
Well, Plato thinks what's going to follow is that we have some
reason to believe in the immortality of the soul as,
again, as we indicated last time, the picture is that the
mind--the soul--is able to grasp these eternal Platonic forms,
the ideas. Typically, we're distracted
from thinking about them by the distractions provided by the
body--the desire for food, drink, sex, what have you,
sleep. But by distancing itself from
the body, the mind, the soul, is able to better
concentrate on the forms. And if you're good at that,
if you practice while you're alive, separating yourself from
the body, then when your body dies,
the mind is able to go up to this Platonic heavenly realm and
commune with gods and other immortal souls and think about
the forms. But if you've not separated
yourself from the body while in life, if you're too enmeshed in
its concerns, then upon the death of your
body your soul will get sucked back in, reincarnated perhaps,
in another body. If you're lucky,
as another person; if you're not so lucky,
as a pig or a donkey or an ant or what have you.
So your goal, Plato says, your goal should
be, in life, to practice death--to separate yourself from
your body. And because of this,
Socrates, who's facing death, isn't distressed at the
prospect, but happy. He's happy that the final
separation will take place and he'll be able to go to heaven.
The dialogue ends, of course, with the death
scene--Socrates has been condemned to death by the
Athenians, and it ends with his drinking
the hemlock, not distressed but rather sort of joyful.
And the dialogue ends with one of the great moving death scenes
in western civilization and as Plato says--let's get the quote
here exactly right--"Of all those we have known,
he was the best and also the wisest and the most upright."
Just before the death scene, there's a long myth,
which I draw your attention to but I don't want to discuss in
any kind of detail. Plato says it's a story;
it's a myth. He's trying to indicate that
there are things that we can't really know in a scientific way
but we can glimpse. And the myth has to do with
these sort of pictures I was just describing where we don't
actually live on the surface of the Earth of in the light,
but rather live in certain hollows in the dark where we're
mistaken about the nature of reality.
Some of you who are maybe familiar with Plato's later
dialogue The Republic may recognize at least what seems to
me, what we have here,
is a foreshadowing of the myth of the cave, or the allegory of
the cave, which Plato describes there as
well. Our concern is going to be the
arguments that make up the center of the dialogue.
Because in the center of the dialogue, before he dies,
Socrates is arguing with his friends.
Socrates is saying, "Look, I'm not worried.
I'm going to live forever." And his disciples and friends
are worried whether this is true or not.
And so the heart of the dialogue consists of a series of
arguments in which Socrates attempts to lay out his reasons
for believing in the immortality of the soul.
And that's going to be our concern.
What I'm going to do is basically run through my attempt
to reconstruct--my attempt to lay out the basic ideas from
this series of four or five arguments that Plato gives us.
I'm going to criticize them. I don't think they work,
though I want to remark before I turn to them that in saying
this I'm not necessarily criticizing Plato.
As we'll see, some of the later arguments
seem to be deliberately aimed at answering objections that we can
raise to some of the earlier arguments.
And so it might well be that Plato himself recognized that
the initial arguments aren't as strong as they need to be.
Plato wrote the dialogues as a kind of learning device,
as a tool to help the reader get better at doing philosophy.
They don't necessarily represent in a systematic
fashion Plato's worked out axiomatic views about the nature
of philosophy. It could be that Plato's
deliberately putting mistakes in earlier arguments so as to
encourage you to think for yourself,
"Oh, this is--here's a problem with this argument.
There's an objection with that argument."
Some of these, Plato then may address later
on. But whether or not he does
address them--we're not doing Plato any honor,
we're not doing him any service,
if we limit ourselves to simply trying to grasp,
here's what Plato thought. We could do the history of
ideas and say, "Here's Plato's views.
Aren't they interesting? Notice how they differ from
Aristotle's views. Aren't they interesting?"
and move on like that. But that's not what the
philosophers wanted us to do. The great philosophers had
arguments that they were putting forward to try to persuade us of
the truths of their positions. And the way you show respect
for a philosopher is by taking those arguments seriously and
asking yourself, do they work or not?
So whether or not the views that are being put forward in
Socrates' mouth are the considered,
reflective judgments of Plato or not, for our purposes we can
just act as though they were the arguments being put forward by
Plato, and we can ask ourselves,
"Do these arguments work or don't they?"
So I'm going to run through a series of these arguments.
I'm going to, as I've mentioned before,
be a bit more exegetical than is normally the case for our
readings. I'm going to actually pause,
periodically look at my notes and make sure I'm remembering
how I think Plato understands the arguments.
Of course, since the dialogue is indeed a dialogue,
we don't always have the arguments laid out with a series
or premises and conclusions. And so it's always a matter of
interpretation, what's the best reconstruction
of the argument he's gesturing towards.
How can we turn it into an argument with premises and
conclusions? Well, that's what I'm going to
try to do for us. Also going to give the
arguments names. These are not names that Plato
gives, but it will make it easy for us to get a fix,
roughly, on the different arguments as we move from one to
the next. So the first argument,
and the worry that gets the whole things going,
is this. So, we've got this nice
Platonic picture where Plato says, "All right.
So the mind can grasp the eternal forms,
but it has to free itself from the body to do that."
And so, the philosopher, who has sort of trained himself
to separate his mind from his body,
to disregard his bodily cravings and desires--the
philosopher will welcome death because at that point he'll
truly, finally, make the final break
from the body. And the obvious worry that gets
raised in the dialogue at this point is this:
How do we know that when the death of the body occurs the
soul doesn't get destroyed as well?
That's the natural worry to have.
Maybe what we need to do is separate ourselves as much as
possible from the influence of our body without actually going
all the way and breaking the connection.
If you think about it like a rubber band, maybe the more we
can stretch the rubber band the better;
but if you stretch too far and the rubber band snaps,
that's not good, that's bad.
It could be that we need the body in order to continue
thinking. We want to free ourselves from
the distractions of the body, but we don't want the body to
die, because when the body dies the soul dies as well.
Even if we are dualists, as we've noticed before--even
if the soul is something different from the body--it
could still be the case, logically speaking,
that if the body gets destroyed, the soul gets
destroyed as well. And so, Socrates' friends ask
him, how can we be confident that the soul will survive the
death of the body and indeed be immortal?
And that's what prompts the series of arguments.
Now, the first such argument I dub "the argument from the
nature of the forms." And the basic thought is fairly
straightforward. The ideas or the forms--justice
itself, beauty itself, goodness itself--the forms are
not physical objects. Right?
We don't ever bump into justice itself.
We bump into societies that may be more or less just,
or individuals who may be more or less just,
but we never bump into justice itself.
The number three is not a physical object.
Goodness itself is not a physical object.
Perfect roundness is not a physical object.
Now, roughly speaking, Socrates' seems to think it's
going to follow straightforwardly from that that
the soul must itself be something non-physical.
If the forms are not physical objects, then Socrates thinks it
follows they can't be grasped. We can certainly think about
the forms, but if they're non-physical they can't be
grasped by something physical like the body.
They've got to be grasped by something non-physical--namely,
the soul. But although that's,
I think, the sketch of where Socrates wants to go,
it doesn't quite give us what we want.
On the one hand, even if it were true that the
soul must be non-physical in order to grasp the non-physical
forms, wouldn't follow that the soul
will survive the death of the body.
That's the problem we've been thinking about for the last
minute. And there's something puzzling.
We might wonder, well, just why is it that the
body can't grasp the forms? So there's a fuller version of
the argument that's the one I want to focus on.
And indeed, I put it up on the board.
So Platonic metaphysics gives us premise number one--that
ideas, forms, are eternal and they're
non-physical. Two--that which is eternal or
non-physical can only be grasped by the eternal and the
non-physical. Suppose we had both of those.
It would seem to give us three, the conclusion we want--that
which grasps the ideas or the forms must be eternal or
non-physical. What is it that grasps the
ideas or the forms? Well, that's the soul.
If that which grasps the ideas or the forms must be
eternal/non-physical, well one thing we're going to
get is, since that which grasps the
forms must be non-physical, the soul is not the body.
Since that which grasps the ideas or forms must be eternal
or non-physical--it's eternal, it's immortal.
All right. Let's look at this again more
carefully. Ideas or forms are eternal;
they're non-physical. Well, I've emphasized the
non-physical aspect, and I've emphasized as well
that they're not changing. But perhaps it's worth taking a
moment to emphasize the eternal aspect of the forms.
Now, people may come and go, but perfect justice--the idea
of perfect justice--that's timeless.
Nothing that happens here on Earth can change or alter or
destroy the number three. Two plus one equaled three
before there were people; two plus one equals three now;
two plus one will always equal three.
The number three is eternal, as well as being non-physical.
So the Platonic metaphysics says quite generally,
if we're thinking about the ideas or the forms,
the point to grasp is they're eternal;
they're non-physical. The crucial premise--since
we're giving Plato number one--the crucial premise for our
purposes is premise number two. Is it or isn't it true that
those things which are eternal or non-physical can only be
grasped by something that is itself eternal and non-physical?
Again, it does seem as though the conclusion that he wants,
number three, follows from that.
If we give him number two, it's going to follow that
whatever's doing the grasping--call that the soul
since the soul is just Plato's word for our mind--if whatever's
doing the grasping of the eternal and non-physical forms
must itself be eternal and non-physical,
it follows that the soul must be non-physical.
So the physicalist view is wrong and the soul must be
eternal. The soul is immortal.
So Socrates has what he wants, once we give him premise number
two, that the eternal, non-physical can only be
grasped by the eternal, non-physical.
As Socrates puts it at one point, "The impure cannot attain
the pure." Bodies--corruptible,
destroyable, physical, passing--whether they
exist or not, whether they exist for a brief
period and then they cease to exist--these impure objects
cannot attain, cannot grasp,
cannot have knowledge of the eternal, changeless non-physical
forms. "The impure cannot attain the
pure." That's the crucial premise,
and what I want to say is, as far as I can see there's no
good reason to believe number two.
Now, number two is not an unfamiliar--premise number two
is not an unfamiliar claim. I take it the claim basically
is that, to put it in more familiar language,
it takes one to know one. Or to use it,
slightly other kind of language that Plato uses at various
points, "Likes are known by likes."
But it takes one to know one is probably the most familiar way
of putting the point. Plato's saying,
"What is it that we know? Well, we know the eternal forms;
takes one to know one. So we must ourselves be
eternal." Unfortunately,
this thought, popular as it may be,
that it takes one to know one, just seems false.
Think about some examples. Well, let's see,
a biologist might study, or a zoologist might study,
cats. Takes one to know one,
so the biologist must himself be a cat.
Well, that's clearly false. You don't have to be feline to
study the feline. Takes one to know one;
so, you can't be a Canadian and study Mexicans,
because it takes one to know one.
Well, that's just clearly stupid.
Of course the Canadians can study the Mexicans and the
Germans can study the French. It does not take one to know
one; to understand the truths about
the French, you do not yourself need to be French.
Or take the fact that some doctors study dead bodies.
Aha! So to study and grasp things
about dead bodies, corpses, you must yourself be a
dead body. No, that certainly doesn't
follow. So if we start actually pushing
ourselves to think about examples--does it really take
one to know one--the answer is, at least as a general claim,
it's not true. It doesn't normally take one to
know one. Now, strictly speaking,
that doesn't prove that premise two is false.
It could still be that, although normally you don't
have to be like the thing that you're studying in order to
study it, although that's not normally
true, it could be that in the particular case of non-physical
objects, in the particular case of
eternal objects, you do have to be eternal,
non-physical to study them. It could be that even though
the general claim, "it takes one to know one" is
false, the particular claim,
"eternal, non-physical can only be grasped by the eternal,
non-physical," maybe that particular claim is true.
And it's only the particular claim that Plato needs.
Still, all I can say is, why should we believe two?
Why should we think there's some--Even though,
normally, the barrier can be crossed and Xs can study the
non-X, why should that barrier
suddenly become un-crossable in the particular instance when
we're dealing with Platonic forms?
Give us some reason to believe premise two.
I can't see any good reason to believe premise two,
and as far as I can see, Plato doesn't actually give us
any reason to believe it in the dialogue.
Consequently, we have to say,
as far as I can see, we haven't been given any
adequate argument for the conclusion that the soul--which
admittedly can think about forms and ideas--we have no good
reason yet to believe, to be persuaded,
that the soul must itself be eternal and non-physical.
That's the first argument. As I say though,
Plato may well recognize the inadequacy of that argument,
because after all Socrates goes on to offer a series of other
arguments. So let's turn to the next.
I call the second argument "the argument from recycling"--not
the best label I suppose, but I've never been able to
come up with a better one. And the basic idea is that
parts get re-used. Things move from one state to
another state and then back to the first state.
So, for example, to give an example that Plato
actually gives in the dialogue, we are all awake now,
but previously we were asleep. We went from being in the realm
of the asleep to being in the realm of the awake,
and we're going to return from the realm of the awake back to
the realm of the asleep and over and over and over again.
Hence, recycling. I think that actually a better
example for Plato's purposes, not that I expect him to have
this particular example, but, would be a car.
Cars are made up of parts that existed before the car itself
existed. There was the engine and the
steering wheel and the tires and so forth.
And these parts got assembled and put together to make up a
car. So the parts of the car existed
prior to the existence of the car itself.
And the time is going to come when the car will cease to exist
but its parts will still be around.
Right? It'll get taken apart for
parts, sold for parts. There will be the distributor
cap, and there will be the tires, and there will be the
carburetor, there will be the steering wheel.
Hence, the name, that I dub the argument,
"the argument from recycling." That's the nature of reality
for Plato. And it seems like a plausible
enough view. Things come into being by being
composed of previously existing parts.
And then, when those things cease to have the form they had,
the parts get used for other purposes.
They get recycled. If we grant that to Plato,
he thinks we've got an argument for the immortality of the soul.
Because after all, what are the parts that make us
up? Well, there are the various
parts of our physical body, but there's also our soul.
Remember, as I said, in introducing the
Phaedo, Plato doesn't so much argue for
the existence of something separate,
the soul, as presuppose it. His fundamental concern is to
try to argue for the immortality of the soul.
So he's just helping himself to the assumption that there is a
soul. It's one of the parts that
makes us, that goes up into making us up,
goes into making us up. It's one of the pieces that
constitutes us. Given the thesis about
recycling, then, we have reason to believe the
soul will continue to exist after we break.
Even after our death, our parts will continue to
exist. Our body continues to exist
even after our death. Our soul will continue to exist.
Well, there's a problem with the argument from recycling,
and it's this. Even if the recycling thesis
shows us that we're made up of something that existed before
our birth and that some kinds of parts are going to have to exist
after our death, we can't conclude that the soul
is one of the parts that's going to continue to exist after our
death.
Consider some familiar facts about human bodies.
As we nowadays know, human bodies are made up of
atoms. And it's certainly true that
the atoms that make up my body existed long before my body
existed. And it's certainly true that
after my death those atoms are going to continue to exist.
So there's some--and will eventually get used to make
something else. So Plato's certainly right
about recycling as a fundamental truth.
The things that make me up existed before,
and will continue to exist after my death.
But that doesn't mean that every part of my body existed
before I was born, and that every part of my body
will continue to exist after I die.
Take my heart. My heart is a part of my body.
Yet, for all that, it didn't exist before my body
began to exist. It came into existence as part
of, along with, the creation of my body,
and it won't continue to exist, at least not very long,
after the destruction of my body.
There'll be a brief period in which, as a cadaver I suppose,
my heart will continue to exist.
But eventually my body will decompose.
We certainly wouldn't have any grounds to conclude my heart is
immortal, will exist forever. That just seems wrong.
So even though it's true that some kind of recycling takes
place, we can't conclude that everything that's now a part of
me will continue to exist afterwards.
It might not have been one of the parts, one of the
fundamental parts, from which I'm built--like the
heart. And if that's right,
if there can be parts that I have now that weren't one of the
parts from which I was made, there's no particular reason to
think it's going to be one of the parts that's going to
continue to exist after I die. Once we see that kind of worry,
we have to see, look, the same thing could be
true for the soul. Even if there is an immortal
soul--Sorry. Even if there is a non-physical
soul that's part of me, we don't yet have any reason to
believe that it's one of the fundamental building blocks that
were being recycled. We don't have adequate reason
to conclude that it's something that existed before I was put
together, it's something that will be
recycled and continue to exist after I fall apart,
after my body decomposes, after I'm separated from my
body, or what have you. Even if recycling takes place,
we don't have any good reason yet to believe that the soul is
one of the recycled parts. So it seems to me "the argument
from recycling," as I call it, is not successful either.
Now, as I say, many times when you read the
dialogue, this or other dialogues by Plato,
it seems as though he's fully cognizant of the objections that
at least an attentive reader will raise about earlier stages
of the argument. Because sometimes the best way
to understand a later argument is to see it as responding to
the weaknesses of earlier arguments.
And I think that's pretty clearly what's going on in the
very next argument that comes up in the dialogue.
The objection I just raised, after all, to the argument from
recycling, said, in effect, even though some
kind of recycling takes place, not all my parts get recycled,
because not all of my parts were among the pre-existing
constituent pieces from which I am built up.
We don't have any particular reason to think my heart's one
of the prior-existing pieces; we don't have any good reason
to assume that my soul's one of the prior-existing pieces.
Well, Plato's very next argument attempts to persuade us
that indeed we do have reason to believe that the soul is one of
the prior-existing pieces. And this argument is known as
"the argument from recollection."
The idea is, he's going to tell us certain
facts that need explaining, and the best explanation
involves a certain fact about recollecting,
or a certain claim about recollecting or remembering.
But we can only remember, he thinks, in the relevant way
if our soul existed before the birth of our body,
before the creation of our body.
All right. What's the crucial fact?
Well, let's start by--Plato starts by telling us,
reminding us of what it is to remember something.
Or perhaps a better word would be what is it to be reminded of
something by something else that resembles it but is not the
thing it reminds you of. I might have a photograph of my
friend Ruth. And looking at the photograph
reminds me of Ruth. It brings Ruth to mind.
I start thinking about Ruth. I remember various things I
know about Ruth. The photograph is able to do
that, is able to trigger these thoughts.
But of course, the photograph is not Ruth.
Right? Nobody would--who's thinking
clearly--would confuse the photograph with my friend.
But the photograph resembles Ruth.
It resembles Ruth well enough to remind me of her,
and interestingly, it can do that even if it's not
a very good photograph. You might hold up the
photograph and I might say, "Gosh, that really doesn't look
very much like Ruth does it?" Even though I see that it is a
photograph of Ruth; it reminds me of her.
Now, how could it be that a photograph reminds me of my
friend? Well, this isn't some deep
mystery. Presumably the way it works is,
as I just said, it looks sort of like her.
It doesn't have to look very much like her.
It looks sort of like her. Your young brother or sister,
or my little children, can draw pictures of family
members that barely look like family members.
My niece drew a picture of my family once when she was three.
It didn't look very much like us at all, but we could sort of
see the resemblance in a vague kind of way, right?
So it's got to look at least somewhat like the missing
friend. But that's not enough.
You've never met Ruth, let's suppose.
I hold up the photograph without having told you anything
about her. The photograph's not going to
remind you of Ruth. Why not?
Well, you don't know Ruth. So the pieces we need are not
only an image of Ruth, even if an imperfect image of
Ruth, we also need some prior acquaintance with Ruth.
That's pretty much what it takes, right?
So on the one hand--temporal sequence--first you know Ruth,
you meet Ruth, you get to know Ruth.
Then at a later time you're shown an image of Ruth--maybe
not even an especially good image of Ruth--but good enough
to remind you. And suddenly,
you're remembering things you know about Ruth.
That's how recollection works.
All right. Now, Plato points out that we
all know things about the Platonic forms.
But the Platonic forms, as we also know,
are not to be found in this world.
The number three is not a physical object,
perfect roundness is not a physical object,
perfect goodness is not a physical object.
We can think about these things; our mind can grasp them,
but they're not to be found in this world.
Yet, various things that we do find in this world get us
thinking about those things.
I look at the plate on my kitchen table,
it's not perfectly round, it's got imperfections;
but suddenly I start thinking about circles,
perfectly round objects. I look at somebody who's pretty.
He or she is not perfectly beautiful, but suddenly I start
thinking about the nature of beauty itself.
Ordinary objects in the world participate to a greater or
lesser degree in the Platonic forms.
That's Plato's picture of metaphysics.
And we bump up against, we look at, we have
interactions with these everyday objects and,
somehow, they get us thinking about the Platonic forms
themselves. How does it happen?
Plato has a theory. He says, "These things remind
us of the Platonic forms." We see something that's
beautiful to some degree, and it reminds us of perfect
beauty. We see something that's more or
less round, and it reminds us of perfect circularity.
We see somebody who's fairly decent morally,
and it reminds us of perfect justice or perfect virtue.
It's just like the photograph, perhaps the not very good
photograph, that reminds me of my friend Ruth.
All right. Well, there's an explanation of
how it could be that things that are not themselves perfectly
round could remind us, could make us think about
perfect roundness. But then Plato says,
"Okay, but keep in mind all of what you need in
order to have reminding, to have recollecting take
place." In order for the photograph to
remind me of Ruth, I have to already have met
Ruth. I have to already be acquainted
with her.
In order for a more or less round plate to remind me of
roundness, Plato says, I have to have already met
perfect roundness itself. In order for a more or less
just society to remind me of justice itself,
so that I can start thinking about the nature of justice
itself, I have to somehow have already
been acquainted with perfect justice.
But how and when did it happen? Not in this life,
not in this world. In this world nothing is
perfectly round, nothing is perfectly beautiful,
nothing is perfectly just. So it's got to have happened
before. If seeing the photograph of my
friend now can remind me of my friend, it's got to be because I
met my friend before. If seeing things that
participate in the forms remind me of the forms,
it's got to be because I've met or been acquainted directly with
the forms before. But you don't bump up against,
you don't meet, you don't see or grasp or
become directly acquainted with, the forms in this life.
So it's got to have happened before this life.
That's Plato's argument. Plato says, thinking about the
way in which we grasp the forms helps us to see that the soul
must have existed before birth, in the Platonic heavenly realm,
directly grasping, directly communing with,
directly understanding the forms.
It's not taking place in this life, so it has to have happened
before. Well, look, now we've got the
kind of argument we were looking for.
Earlier the objection was, we had no good reason to think
the soul was one of the building blocks from which we're
composed; we have no good reason to think
it's one of the pieces that was around before our body got put
together, before our birth. Socrates says, "No.
On the contrary, we do have reason,
based on the argument from recollection,
to conclude that the soul was around before we were born."
All right. So the next question is,
is the argument from recollection a good one?
Now, let's say, I'm not really much concerned
with whether this was an argument that Plato thought
worked or not. Our question is,
do we think it works or not?
Although this is a form of an argument that Plato does put
forward in other dialogues as well,
and so it strikes me so there's at least some reason to think
this is an argument that he felt might well be right.
The crucial premise--Again, we're going to just grant Plato
the metaphysics. The crucial question is going
to be, is it right that in order to explain how it is we could
have knowledge of the forms now that we have to appeal to a
prior existence in which we had direct acquaintance?
It's not obvious to me that that's true.
It's not obvious to me for a couple of reasons.
One question is this: Is it really true that in order
to think about the perfectly straight,
I must have somehow, somewhere at some point come up
against, had direct knowledge of,
the perfectly straight? Isn't it enough for me to
extrapolate from cases that I do come up against in this life?
I come across things that are bent;
I come across things that are more straight,
more and more straight. Can't my mind take off from
there and push straight ahead to the idea of the perfectly
straight, even if I never have encountered it before?
Let me stop with this idea. Even if Plato is right,
that we need to have acquaintance with the Platonic
forms themselves in order to think about them,
and even if Plato is right that we never get the acquaintance in
this world, in the interaction with
ordinary physical objects, why couldn't it be that our
acquaintance with the Platonic forms comes about in this life
for the very first time? That's the question,
or that's the objection, that we'll turn to at the start
of next class.